Renee Gerlich and Charlie Montague at Pride Parade, Auckland 2018 (Photo by Arthur Francisco)
There was a similar post put up on the 'Young Greens' facebook page, which also also accused both Renee Gerlich and Charlie Montague of advocating funding cuts to LGBT youth groups 'Inside Out' and 'Rainbow Youth'. It has now been removed. Here is a screenshot:
In response to these accusations I wrote a letter to several Green party leaders. The following is a copy of that letter, with hyperlinks to articles backing up my claims:
To Whom It May Concern:
As a Green party supporter
with many friends and family members who have actively participated in the
party, I am very concerned and saddened by the Green party response to the
actions of Charlie Montague and Renee Gerlich at the recent Pride parade. On both the
‘Young Greens’ and ‘Rainbow Greens’ facebook pages there are posts which claim
that Montague and Gerlich advocate funding cuts to Inside Out and Rainbow Youth,
and that the protest banner they carried amounts to an attack on trans
identifying people. Both of these claims are false, and act to prohibit democratic
and critical debate about an important issue. Emotions often run high in these
debates, but that is all the more reason not to condone lies and smear tactics.
The protest banner carried by Montague and Gerlich read “Stop Giving Kids Sex Hormones – Protect Lesbian Youth”.
There is a real and substantive issue here about the physical side effects of
synthetic hormones and puberty blocking drugs such as Lupron. Worldwide the
numbers of children and youth who identify as transgender has skyrocketed only
very recently. There are therefore no long term scientific studies on the
potential side effects of these drugs. Yet existing studies on Hormone
replacement therapy for menopausal women, and the numerous severe side effects
on many people who have used puberty suppressants, are cause to take concerns
about this issue very seriously.
There are also numerous
studies which indicate that the vast majority of young people who experience gender
dysphoria during their youth go on to identify as gay or lesbian adults. In
countries such as the US and the UK, where the medicalised approach towards
gender non-conformity is well entrenched, there is a growing movement of ‘de-transitioners’
who have come to the realisation that the medical approach did not work for them. The majority of these people are young women who now identify as lesbian.
Clearly there are complex and
contentious political issues around these questions. The perspective held by many
trans-identifying people is very different from the feminist analysis of Charlie Montague and Renee Gerlich. So by all means encourage and support members
who wish to debate this important issue, clearly it deserves considered and
careful attention. What it does not need is lies and smear tactics.
Yours Sincerely,
Tim Leadbeater
|
Tuesday, 20 February 2018
Open Letter to the Green Party regarding Feminist protest action at Pride 2018
Saturday, 1 July 2017
Open Letter to the PPTA: Why is discussion about the medicalisation of gender off-limits?
I recently read an opinion piece in
the PPTA magazine by Lizzie Marvelly about the so called ‘bathroom battle’ over
transgender students and their access to toilets and facilities which match
their gender identities. Because I strongly disagreed with Marvelly’s
perspective on and framing of the issues involved in this discussion, I was
motivated to write a reply. Unfortunately the PPTA News editor did not accept
my piece, so I am reprinting it here because I doubt that any attempt to revise
my argument would satisfy the stringent conditions the PPTA places on debate
about transgender issues. I believe that the PPTA News editor has refused to publish my piece for ideological reasons. I will also argue that this refusal to allow debate amounts to a violation of one of the key stipulations in the PPTA's Code of Ethics.
Here is the article I submitted:
In a recent article published
through the PPTA, Lizzie Marvelly called the gender “bathroom battle” a “front
for intolerance”.
Marvelly is right to say that
schools should support and respect their LGBTQ+ students. Bigotry, intolerance
and bullying behaviour needs to be challenged and does not have any place in
our schools. I’m proud to work at a school that has a thriving ‘Rainbow Youth’
club, where many students take part in events such as the ‘pink shirt’ day
supporting tolerance and respect for gender non conforming people.
I also agree with Marvelly’s
contention that the bathroom battle is ‘proxy war’ with much deeper issues in
the background.
Marvelly’s portrayal of these
issues is problematic, though, for a number of reasons.
It may well be that Family First,
her target for criticism, is a conservative organisation with values
opposed to LGBTQ+ rights. Yet whatever the background motivations of Family
First, I struggle to understand how the concerns of female students can be so
flippantly thrown out with the bathwater as ‘bigotry’.
The recent case of a male
transgender student gaining access to female facilities at Marlborough Girl’s
College is a case in point. Laura, the student who spoke out last year against
the granting of this access, does not speak the language of bigotry. Laura’s
mother referred to the ‘vulnerability’ of teenage girls, and insisted that
males and females are ‘built differently’ and therefore need private spaces. Laura
said that she and her peers were not consulted, and talked about the ‘stressful
and embarrassing’ time girls can go through during puberty, and their increased
need for privacy from boys. She said that younger girls with a history of abuse
or trauma would be particularly sensitive and ‘triggered’ by the presence of
males inside their toilet facilities. In the AUT youtube video Marvelly
mentions, many of the women who spoke out against the wholesale replacement of
female only facilities voiced concerns based on their cultural values. None of
these were motivated by bigotry.
Another important background issue
is the debate surrounding the identification of transgender children. Many feminists are critical of the medicalised approach towards gender non-conforming
youth. They point to the gender stereotypes implicit in much of this
identification, and question the appropriateness and effectiveness of physical
transition. Lupron, the puberty blocking drug sometimes prescribed to
transgender identified children, has a number of very serious potential side effects. Taken in conjunction with synthetic hormones, Lupron causes permanent
sterilisation. Other potential effects include higher risks for chronic pain,
osteoporosis, depression and anxiety. There are unanswered questions about the
magnitude and extent of these risks because few scientific studies have been
carried out, and the fact that the population of medically transitioned people
has only very recently begun to increase dramatically. The long term effects of
drugs such as Lupron and the ongoing use of synthetic hormones are still
largely unknown - and this spells medical experimentation.
This medicalised approach towards
gender non-conformity goes hand-in-glove with the concept of a free-floating
‘gender identity’ which sometimes gets mixed up in the ‘wrong body’. Young
boys, for example, who like to play with dolls and wear pink are encouraged by
this ideology to identify as girls trapped in a boys’ body.
How does this ideology connect to
the bathroom battle? I am worried that promoting access to previously
sex-segregated spaces such as toilets based on ‘gender identity’ will
effectively normalise and validate this contentious ideology.
Do we really need to add to all the
pain and turmoil teenagers experience during puberty by suggesting the
possibility that their troubles are due to them being born in the ‘wrong’ body?
Is this even possible?
It seems clear that gender identity
ideology, not ‘bigotry’, is the bogeyman lurking in the shadows of this debate.
* *
The reply explaining why my piece
was refused I found deeply disturbing. Clearly my views on this issue are at
odds with the PPTA News editor, but I am certain that I am not the only PPTA
member out there with similar questions and concerns. Shutting down debate and
discussion about an issue which directly affects the wellbeing of some our most
vulnerable students seems to me clearly at odds with the PPTA Code of Ethics,
which demands that teachers “help all pupils to develop their potentialities
for personal growth”. How can we do that if we cannot even have a debate when
the views about how that growth can best be fostered are so hotly contested?
The really depressing reason behind
this is that the PPTA News editor is completely convinced that my views are
based on prejudice and intolerance:
A piece that
questions whether such a thing as being transgender is ‘even possible’ and
refers to gender diversity as ideology is not something we would run given we
have members who fit into these groups and work with these students. We have
democratically agreed guidelines affirming students with diverse genders and
sexualities and we don’t want to negate our work supporting all of our members.
I wonder what exactly ‘gender
diversity’ is, and why it is wrong to call it an ‘ideology’? I never used the
phrase in my piece, and I’m not sure of the answer to either of these
questions. What I am very clear about is what I object to and why. ‘Gender
identity ideology’ as I understand it involves the idea that people can be born
into the “wrong” body. There is typically some kind of appeal to the notion of
gendered brains or ‘essences’ which somehow get misplaced inside a body which does
not match up. The medicalised model of ‘gender affirmation’ via things like
synthetic hormones and surgery is the practical consequence of this idea,
together with the assumption that the body is more ‘plastic’ than the mind.
I don’t believe in gendered brains,
gender essences or the assumption that the body is more plastic than the mind.
I reject these ideas not out of ‘bigotry’ but because I believe that they do
not withstand scientific scrutiny, and also because I believe that these ideas
seriously undermine and negate critical feminist perspectives on gender.
I strongly believe that gay,
lesbian and gender non conforming youth should be supported and validated. I also
believe that there is absolutely nothing ‘wrong’ about the bodies of any of
these young people. I don’t believe that their bodies benefit from breast
binders, puberty blockers or synthetic hormones. I don’t believe that they
should be sterilised.
Clearly my beliefs at are at odds
with the PPTA News editor, and many others who embrace the medicalised gender
identity model. There is a debate to be had. Lots of people and organisations
have interests and agendas here – the drug companies and medical institutions
who profit from medicalising gender, parents of GNC children, feminist critics
and of course the children and youth who experience the real and acute pain of gender
dysphoria. I’m a parent of two young children and a teacher of teenagers. I have
an interest in this debate too as a human being and as a teacher who takes
seriously the stipulation in the PPTA Code of Ethics – let’s repeat it again:
Teachers should help all pupils to develop their potentialities for
personal growth
This is what the PPTA News editor
says about this important debate:
‘We also feel it
would be irresponsible to publish comments on side effects of specific
medications as we are not medical professionals.’
Well I’m not a medical professional
either. All I can do is read books and internet articles on this topic. I’m
sure there are many science teachers out there who read the PPTA News and also
know a huge amount more than I do about endocrinology, human biology and the
effects of puberty blockers. But of course we cannot even begin to discuss any
of this, because the people in charge of the PPTA News are not medical professionals.
We can talk about toilets and the
conservative bigotry of Family First, but we can’t talk about the physical
effects of breast binding. (I bring this up because the ‘Rainbow Youth’
facebook page recently featured an advertisement which celebrated these
devices - see also Renee Gerlich's piece for more on this topic). This is what a ‘top surgery’ specialist has to say about breast binders:
If you are
considering long-term chest binding, then there are some important things to
keep in mind. This following are the three biggest health consequences of chest
binding that you need to be aware of before you do begin.
Compressed Ribs
One of the biggest
health consequence of chest binding is compressed or broken ribs, which can
lead to further health problems. Unfortunately, you can fracture the ribs fairy
easily so you should avoid binding your chest using bandages or tapes, as these
can be unsafe.
Compressing your
chest too tightly or incorrectly can permanently damage small blood vessels.
This can cause blood flow problems and increase the risk of developing blood
clots. Over time, this can lead to inflamed ribs (costochondritis) and even a
heart attack due to decreased blood flow to the heart.
The following
are some symptoms you should look out for:
·
Loss of breath
·
Back pain throughout the back or shoulders
·
Increased pain or pressure with deep breaths
Collapsed Lungs
Since chest
binding can lead to fractured ribs, this can increase the risk of puncturing or
collapsing a lung. This happens when a broken rib punctures the lung, causing
serious health issues.
Once the lung is
punctured, it has a higher risk of collapsing because air can fill the spaces around
the lungs and chest.
Back Problems
If you bind your
chest too tightly then it can cause serious back issues by compressing the
spine, which is part of your central nervous system. The spine controls many
functions, and you need to be very careful when doing anything that may cause
damage.
Back pain from
chest binding can also be an indication that a lung has been injured. If the
pain is coming from the upper back or shoulder, consult with a doctor for
further examination to ensure proper lung health.
Fractured ribs,
damaged blood vessels, or punctured lungs can cause difficulties down the line
and may stop you from being able to move forward with surgery. Keeping these
issues in mind will allow you get the most out of using chest binding.
Discuss chest
binding with an expert to ensure that you get the best results, reduce the risk
of complications, and create optimal health for you.
If you are a PPTA member, please
don’t talk about any of this. We can’t debate this because we are not medical
professionals. It’s much nicer and easier to just get Lizzie Marvelly in to
talk about toilets. That way we don’t have to deal with any of the hard
questions. Please don’t worry too much about the stipulation in the PPTA Code
of Ethics – let’s repeat it again just for good measure:
Teachers should help all pupils to develop
their potentialities for personal growth
Don’t worry about Lupron either.
You’re probably not a ‘medical professional’, so you shouldn’t even be trying
to read or understand the scientific literature on this topic. Please ignore
and do not dare to discuss with the PPTA facts such as:
Unproven: Lupron
Depot is unproven and not medically necessary for puberty suppression in
patients with gender identity disorder due to the lack of long-term safety
data. Statistically robust randomized controlled trials are needed to address
the issue of whether the benefits outweigh the substantial inherent clinical
risk in its use.
Of course it could be true that for
some gender dysphoric teens, the medical treatment model might be the only
thing that works for them. This is complex and difficult territory, and I am
sure that the PPTA News Editor would not encourage any debate around the issues
involved. We should not consider, talk about or debate the surveys which
indicate that about 80% of gender dysphoric youth desist from transgender
identification by the time they become adults. You should not read this article which scrutinises the debate around this statistical claim, and concludes:
Every study that
has been conducted on this has found the same thing. At the moment there is
strong evidence that even many children with rather severe gender dysphoria
will, in the long run, shed it and come to feel comfortable with the bodies
they were born with. The critiques of the desistance literature presented by
Tannehill, Serano, Olson and Durwood, and others don’t come close to debunking
what is a small but rather solid, strikingly consistent body of research.
Well, I see that I have gone way
over the 250 word limit for letters to the PPTA News, and for obvious reasons I
know you will not even consider publishing this anyway. It’s a shame that this
discussion has to be limited to blogs. If any PPTA members are actually reading
this, I would encourage them to read some of the recent pieces by Renee Gerlich on this issue. I would also encourage them to contemplate the meaning and moral
force of the stipulation in the PPTA Code of Ethics, which I will repeat once
again in conclusion:
Teachers should help all pupils to develop their potentialities for
personal growth
Monday, 27 February 2017
The Case Against Gender: a review of Sheila Jeffreys’ Gender Hurts
- Jeffreys, Sheila. (2014). Gender Hurts, London and New York: Routledge
- Hausman, Bernice L. (1995). Changing Sex: Transexuality, Technology and the Idea of Gender, Durham and London: Duke University Press
I shall postpone necessary preliminary
remarks and dive head-first into the juicy outrageous bits. Jeffreys pulls no
punches, and combines academic analysis with shocking and uncomfortable
anecdotes and images. There are no ‘trigger warnings’, and her robust,
matter-of-fact style will appear shocking to some readers. Under the section
heading ‘Surgery for male-bodied transgenders’, we learn of the difficulties
experienced by people with surgically constructed vaginas:
In one case […]
the skin of the scrotum that had been used in the constructed vagina had not
had electrolysis to remove the pubic hair and the hair grew inside the vagina:
‘One day I was making love and something didn’t feel right. There was this
little ball of hair like a Brillo pad in my vagina.’ A surgeon pulled the hair
out of him but warned it would continually grow back[i].
Gender
Hurts devotes an entire chapter to the experiences of women married to men
who transgender in middle age. Typically, these are heterosexual men with a
fetish for cross-dressing. They tend to embrace stereotypical notions of
femininity, and their practices place great strain on their wives. Jeffreys
describes the experience of Helen Boyd, a women with critical sensibilities who
‘never knew exactly what feeling like a woman was supposed to mean and rejected
femininity as socially constructed and constricting’:
…her husband
told her he did know what it was to feel like a woman, and it was certainly not
what she had ever felt. She explains: “The more I encouraged him to find an
identity that felt comfortable and natural to him, the more unnatural he seemed
to me. His manners changed, as did the way he used his hands. He flipped his
hair and started using a new voice.” She hoped his behaviour was just a “phase”
because “I felt as if I were living with Britney Spears. It was like sleeping
with the enemy[ii].”
Another chapter is devoted to the
issue of women’s spaces, and the morally aggressive politics of the transgender
lobby to gain male access to these spaces. The Michigan Womyn’s Music Festival,
a women’s only event which has been running since 1976, has been repeatedly
targeted by transgender activists. In 2010 the tactics used became
‘particularly violent and aggressive’:
Camp Trans […]
“vandalised the festival and threatened festival goers”. A flyer being
distributed by the activists showed a rather extraordinary degree of woman
hating: “A hot load from my monstrous tranny-cock embodies womanhood more than
the pieces of menstrual [sic] art
your transphobic cunts could ever hope to create[iii]”.
Taken together these three examples
sum up Jeffreys’ case against the politics and ideology of transgenderism. She
argues that this ideology and its associated practices harm trans people, women
and the feminist movement. Gender non conforming children are encouraged to
identify as ‘trans’ and risk major health consequences, and gay and lesbian people
also suffer. Her arguments are based
around an historical account of transgenderism as a socially constructed
phenomenon which grew out of medical practices relating to intersex people and
an associated discourse which created the concept of ‘gender identity’. It is
this historical account which I will focus on and elaborate, but before I do
this I will say a few words about the political context of Gender Hurts and some of the critical comments made about this
book.
The political battle between
radical feminists and transgender advocates is heated and Jeffreys’ text is
without doubt a weapon, a polemic directed straight at both the heart and mind
of the reader. The uncompromising use of ‘pronouns of origin’ instead of those preferred by transgender people, the claim that male power is the driving
force behind the politics of transgenderism and the insistence that women
should create and protect female only spaces – these tenets are all articulated
in both an academic and deeply personal register. No wonder then that Gender Hurts provoked a vitriolic
response from offended liberals, who denounced it as a politically reactionary exercise in
transphobic hate speech. Most of the reviews I read barely engaged with the
arguments made in the text, and tended to cast aspersions upon the scholarly
and moral integrity of the book instead of explaining why they thought
Jeffreys’ ideas and concerns were wrong and unwarranted. Tim R. Johnston, for
example, states that:
Jeffreys relies on a very small, controversial,
and often outdated set of texts and evidence to support her arguments. She does
not acknowledge the controversial or contested nature of this evidence, nor
does she entertain significant and established evidence that is critical of her
position. Second, the tone of the book is extremely disrespectful, and there
are several places where Jeffreys engages in significant misrepresentations of
transgender people, their allies, and research. These problems call into
question not only the book's academic integrity, but also Jeffreys's scholarly
objectivity and rigor.
In a review which is best described as apoplectic and
somewhat unhinged, ‘Overland’ reviewer Lia
Incognita simply refuses to engage with any of Jeffreys’ arguments on moral
grounds. Because Gender Hurts commits
the cardinal sin of not accepting the truth of the statement ‘transwomen are
women’, it is simply impossible that any of the arguments have any merit whatsoever.
The closest she gets to engaging with the text is through quoting Judith Butler, who very clearly has not read the book herself:
“If she makes use of social construction as a theory to support
her view, she very badly misunderstands its terms. In her view, a trans
person is ‘constructed’ by a medical discourse and therefore is the victim of a
social construct. But this idea of social constructs does not acknowledge
that all of us, as bodies, are in the active position of figuring out how to
live with and against the constructions – or norms – that help to form
us. We form ourselves within the vocabularies that we did not choose, and
sometimes we have to reject those vocabularies, or actively develop new ones.
[...]
One problem with that view of social construction is that it
suggests that what trans people feel about what their gender is, and should be,
is itself ‘constructed’ and, therefore, not real. And then the feminist
police comes along to expose the construction and dispute a trans person’s
sense of their lived reality. I oppose this use of social construction
absolutely, and consider it to be a false, misleading, and oppressive use of
the theory.”
In order to clarify my thoughts on these objections to
Gender Hurts, I carefully examined
the social construction arguments made by Jeffreys’ and the texts she uses to
develop her case. The most important book she refers to is Bernice L. Hausman’s
Changing Sex: Transsexualism, Technology,
and the Idea of Gender. I think Butler seriously misrepresents Jeffreys’ account
of social construction, and I shall explain why as I outline the most important
elements of the account.
Jeffreys argues that it is possible to articulate a
social construction account of transgenderism along similar lines to that of
homosexuality as famously described by Michel Foucault. Just as scientific
theories and medical descriptions wove themselves into nineteenth century
social relations to create an essentialised and naturalised category of persons
(homosexuals), the twentieth century contains a distinct yet parallel story
concerning the creation of transgenderism. The social identities created
through these discursive processes are shaped by the over-arching imperatives
of a patriarchal system of male dominance and heteronormativity:
The creation of the
transgender role can be seen as a way of separating off unacceptable gender
behaviour which might threaten the system of male domination and female
subordination, from correct gender behaviour, which is seen as suitable for
persons of a particular biological sex. In the case of homosexuality, the
effect is to shore up the idea of exclusive and natural heterosexuality; and,
in the case of transgenderism, the naturalness of sex roles[iv].
Unlike homosexuality, transgenderism required the
existence of particular types of specialised medical technology. Developments
in endocrinology (the field of medicine relating to hormones and hormone
therapy), anaesthetics and plastic surgery occurred in the first half of the
twentieth century. These developments influenced the treatment of intersex
people, who were now subject to medical procedures to ‘correct’ their ambiguous
sex. Whereas it is most certainly appropriate to label intersex infants as ‘victims’
of medical technology, it is not at all true that transgender people were
similarly passive recipients of medical treatment. Jeffreys is most definitely
not guilty of the sin of denying ‘agency’ to transgender people. It is this
very agency which forms a crucial plank in the social construction account:
Hausman explains
that when there was public knowledge about medical advances and technological
capabilities individuals could then name themselves as ‘the’ appropriate
subjects of particular medical interventions, and thereby participate in the
construction of themselves as patients[v].
Both Hausman and Jeffreys describe the ideological processes
and changes which accompanied this construction of a ‘born in the wrong body’
subject. Hausman provides us with an acute and insightful view into the
pre-requisite assumptions required for sex change medical procedures:
To advocate
hormonal and surgical sex change as a therapeutic tool for those whose ‘gender
identifications’ are at odds with their anatomical sex, it is necessary to
believe that physiological interventions have predictable psychological
effects. In order to do this, evidence of the unpredictable psychological
effects of plastic surgery must be marginalised, understood as aberrant
(neurotic or psychotic) reactions, or controllable through patient selection –
and certainly not the norm. It is necessary to believe, further, that patient
‘happiness’ is a recognisable and realizable goal for surgeries that have no
physiological indication. And, in addition, it is necessary to acknowledge a
certain autonomy of the psychological realm such that the psyche is understood
as the realm of stability and certainty, while the body is deemed mutable[vi].
It is worth pausing here to take in
and consider Hausman’s perspective. To question the fact that people seek
medical procedures which help ‘align’ their anatomy with their gender identity
is currently viewed as tantamount to a fascist hate crime. Yet clearly there
are a host of quite unique and questionable metaphysical ideas which make such
facts possible. Usually people seek medical treatment for physical ailments,
and psychological treatment for mental distress. There are of course drug
treatments for people with severe mental illnesses, but these are informed by a
lively debate about the relative merits of different treatment approaches.
Medicalisation of psychiatric conditions is a political subject of debate when
it comes to things like drug treatments for depression, but such debate is a
moral taboo when it comes to gender issues. Gender identity advocates insist
that there is absolutely nothing ‘pathological’ about seeking medical treatment
for gender dysphoria. This moral position very effectively silences any debates
about the nature and causes of gender related distress.
These metaphysical assumptions
which underlie the medicalised treatment model were facilitated by the
development of ‘gender’ and ‘gender identity’ as discursive entities which
became progressively removed from material biological reality. This process
started in the early twentieth century with the treatment of intersex infants,
and reached its peak in the 1950s and 1960s with the work of John Money, Joan
Hampson and John Hampson. Prior to the 1950s the word ‘gender’ was an obscure
grammatical term, and was not a part of everyday parlance. The phrase ‘gender
identity’ entered the world in 1964, in an academic paper written by a
psychologist[vii].
Jeffreys argues that this discursive development facilitated the normalisation
of the transgender subject:
Hausman argues that
the ‘production of the concept of gender in Western culture’ can be analysed.
All of the medical ‘interventions’ […] depended upon ‘the construction of a
rhetorical system that posits a prior, gendered self necessary to justify
surgical interventions[viii]’
Hausman’s account also casts the
dependence the other way around, so that medical practices and gender discourse
mutually support each other:
… the semiotic
shift from sex to gender, from body to mind, relied on the use of plastic
surgical technologies as treatments for impaired psychological functioning[ix].
Again it is worth pausing and taking stock of the
implications of Hausman’s view. She is not in any sense ‘discounting’ or ‘erasing’
the lived reality of people who come to think of themselves as born in the
wrong body. She is instead clarifying the historical conditions of possibility
for such beliefs to exist. These historical conditions involve both medical
technology and a very particular type of gender discourse. Both Jeffreys and
Hausman are severely critical of the view that transgender identities can be retrospectively located throughout history and across different cultures in
various types of ‘third genders’. Transgender identities are a specific product of the twentieth century.
Hausman describes how the discourse on gender shifted from a
social to a private and individualistic register. ‘Gender’ was conceptualised
as both a set of social roles and stereotypes, and as a private essence inside
people which develops over time. Because intersex people frequently experienced
great suffering when their internal sense of gender did not match their
assigned social role, the medical approach was to ‘fix’ the anatomy to line up
gender identity with sex. Psychologists and sexologists increasingly emphasised
the notion of gender identity, rather than gender roles, and came to view
gender identity as something that was fairly rigidly ‘imprinted’ on the mind in
early childhood. Hausman explains the problematic consequences of this ‘imprinting’
model:
To suggest that
socially constructed behaviours are imprinted,
that is, established irrevocably and without flexibility, is, however, to lend
tacit support to culturally hegemonic rules and expectations. The concept of
imprinted behaviour suggests the idea that while there is one correct pattern
(heterosexuality with its concomitant masculine or feminine gender role
expression), this pattern can be wrongly imprinted. Because the notion of
imprinting suggests irrevocably established behaviours, the only way to affect
(or ‘cure’) the anomalous imprint – so that the subject can engage in cultural
activities as a ‘normal’ person – is to alter some other aspect of the subject.
In the context of intersexuality, after gender role has been imprinted, the
subject’s genital morphology and hormonal makeup become targets for medical
intervention. The same holds true for transsexualism and it is in this
connection that transsexualism appropriated one of its strongest arguments for
surgical and hormonal sex change, as transsexuals are understood to be subjects
who for some reason develop the ‘wrong’ gender identity for their anatomical
sex[x].
Sheila Jeffreys observes that the majority of people who
argued for these sex change procedures were male, and argues that the male
character of the demand for access to medical treatment is a defining feature
of transgenderism. She traces the history of this demand, from famous early
cases in the 1950s such as Christine Jorgensen to the ‘pioneer’ efforts of
cross dresser Virginia Price in the 1960s and 1970s. Following the controversial studies of Blanchard and Bailey, she distinguishes between
homosexual men who transition and heterosexual men who are motivated by autogynephilia (an erotic fetish for dressing in women’s clothing). Jeffreys
argues that we should not accept the separation between gender identity and
sexuality as unproblematic, and that feminists should be wary of the motives of
men who transition.
Considering Butler’s criticism of Jeffreys’ view, it is true
that Jeffreys supports a sort of ‘feminist policing’. Women are justified,
according to Jeffreys, in rejecting the presence of male transgenders inside
spaces such as toilets and changing rooms, and a part of this justification has
to do with the prevalence of autogynephilia. Women are also justified to be
critical of the views put forward by male transgender ‘feminists’ such as Julia Serano. She recounts the experience of Serano who wrapped a lacy white curtain
around his eleven year old body like a dress, satisfying a deeply felt urge to
feel ‘feminine’. Noting that his experience is “unlikely to have been shared by
many females”, Jeffreys ruthlessly exposes Serano’s efforts to “reinvent ‘feminism’
to fit his erotic interests[xi]”.
What is at stake here is not the ‘reality’ of social constructions, but rather
the male power and patriarchal structuring of sexuality which informs the undenied reality of those same constructions.
* * *
Sheila Jeffreys’ forthright and
uncompromising feminist stance is tempered somewhat by her admission in the
introduction that most of the literature on the transgender phenomenon is
celebratory rather than critical, and that she had to read ‘against the grain’ in
order to develop her account. Relying in part on the burgeoning scene of radical feminist bloggers critical of the current political climate surrounding
transgender issues, Gender Hurts is
best viewed as hybrid of academic theory and political polemic. Coming in at
under 200 pages, it is a ‘monograph’ which left me dissatisfied, not because of
its critical sensibility but because of its brevity. There may well be holes in
Jeffreys’ arguments and shortcomings in her account, but Gender Hurts deserves considered recognition and engagement, not
abuse and dismissal.
[i] Jeffreys, Sheila. (2014). Gender Hurts, London and New York:
Routledge, p.70
[ii]
Ibid. p.93
[iii]
Ibid.p.168
[iv]
Ibid. p.17
[v]
Ibid. p.21
[vi]
Hausman, Bernice L. (1995). Changing Sex: Transexuality, Technology and
the Idea of Gender, Durham and London: Duke University Press, p.63
[vii]
Robert Stoller, ‘A Contribution to the Study of Gender Identity’, Journal of
the American Medical Association 45 (1964): 220 – 26
[viii]
Ibid. p.27
[ix]
Ibid. p68
[x]
Ibid. p.101
[xi]
Ibid. p. 50
Sunday, 26 February 2017
Transplaining Spin: Fact-checking the liberal reaction to Ask Me First
The Spinoff news site has recently published two
articles in response to the Family First ‘Ask Me First’ campaign. Laura,
a student, has expressed
concern about Marlborough Girls College's decision to allow a male transgender student use of
the female toilet facilities. Supported by her mother and the conservative
lobby group Family First, she appeared recently in a Family First video speaking
out against the school’s decision and the lack of consultation with students
and families. Both articles strongly condemn Laura's stance, and paint her actions as a part of a bullying transphobic campaign against a powerless and vulnerable trans student. They both claim that there are no safety concerns for the female students, whereas there are major safety concerns for the trans student.
Is it true that the safety concerns lie squarely on the side of the trans student, and that people who question this narrative are transphobic bullies? Is it true that the trans student is relatively powerless and deserves more moral consideration than students such as Laura?
Is it true that the safety concerns lie squarely on the side of the trans student, and that people who question this narrative are transphobic bullies? Is it true that the trans student is relatively powerless and deserves more moral consideration than students such as Laura?
The first Spinoff article, written by Television editor Alex Casey with a palpable sense of
delicious moral outrage, denies the claim that there was no consultation
process. She interviews transactivist Lexie Matheson, who paints a rosy picture
of ‘unity’ at the school, and claims that the ‘school consulted widely,
they consulted the community, they consulted the students and the student LGBT
groups, I was able to talk to most kids and see the students in her classroom.’
He goes on to categorically state:
Everybody was asked first. The school was fantastic in terms
of talking to the community, sending emails and newsletters out and talking to
anyone with concerns. Many people did came to me with concerns about how it
would affect them. The answer, of course, is that it doesn’t affect you at all.
This directly contradicts the account given by Laura and her
mother. From the recent
Herald article on February 22nd:
Laura's mother says the school's claims that it considered
the rights of all its students before making the decision are "really
incorrect".
"They have not respected the value of the girls'
vulnerability. They haven't respected their thoughts on the matter. There's
over 600 girls. They also have a right to have a voice.
"I think as a parent, we should've got together in the
school itself before it all happened. Why didn't they ask us what we wanted to
do?"
Laura adds that while she has nothing against the
transgender student involved in the stoush, she takes issue with the school's
lack of consideration of her views.
"[The school] never asked me my opinion. They never
respected my rights. Nobody asked me first."
So which version of events is true? Were the parents and
students asked about the decision to allow a male student to use the girls’
facilities? Was there a warm, loving glow of tolerance which enveloped the
entire school in support of the transgender student, Stephani Rose Muollo-Gray?
Were the only exceptions to this enlightened and harmonious community small pockets
of close-minded fundamentalist Christian bigots, hatefully opposed to
transgender bathroom rights?
If you read Muollo-Gray’s statement which accompanied his petition
to allow his use of female facilities from June last year, a very different
picture emerges. He states that he started off using the female toilets, but
was challenged by a teacher for doing this and subsequently had a series of
meetings with the principal about the issue. The principal had originally made
it a condition that Muollo-Gray should use the unisex toilets provided by the
school, but Muollo-Gray had no recollection of making this agreement. The
statement makes it very clear that there was a lengthy process of debate and
discussion, and that the school authorities were initially opposed to
Muollo-Gray’s demand:
Several other meetings occurred with very little progress.
They kept trying to tell me that I couldn’t use the girls’ bathrooms because it
was all about everyone’s comfort and safety, as though anyone was at risk from
me just trying to use the bathroom. The one idea that they kept using as an
excuse as to why I could only use the few gender neutral or male bathrooms in
the school was that it would make some students uncomfortable, and that they
would complain and parents would become involved.
The petition gained 6,889 supporters and the story was widely
reported in the local and national media. The school soon changed its
policy and Muollo-Gray was allowed to use the female facilities. There is no
evidence that I could find of any sort of consultation process or vote about
the issue. The most plausible story is that the school changed its policy
because of the media spotlight and the pressure of the lobby groups in support
of Muollo-Gray.
A second claim made by both of the articles is that
excluding Muollo-Gray from female facilities would compromise his safety at the
school.
Lexie Matheson states: “The primary concern is safety and
feeling validated and authentic in yourself. … There is new research
coming out that often young transgender women often have more bladder
infections than the general population because we hold on for too long. We wait
until there’s nobody around and then we go to the bathroom, and that’s really
unhealthy and really unsafe.”
In the second article, Scout Barbour Evans states that: “…the Youth ’12 report – a report on the wellbeing of transgender youth in Aotearoa – has shown that 53.5% of trans youth are worried for their own safety at school. 17.6% of them are bullied at school at least weekly, and 19.8% of trans young people had attempted suicide in the last year. These are really, really alarming statistics. …everyone is focused on this theoretical, abstract debate about whether or not transgender people should be allowed to pee outside of their own homes, while our transgender rangatahi are suffering in a real, tangible way. We know from seeing the Safe Schools and marriage equality plebiscite debacle in Australia that when this sort of bullying happens by media, the overall wellbeing of our LGBTQ rangatahi goes down.”
In the second article, Scout Barbour Evans states that: “…the Youth ’12 report – a report on the wellbeing of transgender youth in Aotearoa – has shown that 53.5% of trans youth are worried for their own safety at school. 17.6% of them are bullied at school at least weekly, and 19.8% of trans young people had attempted suicide in the last year. These are really, really alarming statistics. …everyone is focused on this theoretical, abstract debate about whether or not transgender people should be allowed to pee outside of their own homes, while our transgender rangatahi are suffering in a real, tangible way. We know from seeing the Safe Schools and marriage equality plebiscite debacle in Australia that when this sort of bullying happens by media, the overall wellbeing of our LGBTQ rangatahi goes down.”
Both Matheson and Barbour Evans speak very generally, but
appear to be saying that without access to female facilities, Muollo-Gray would
be at greater risk of suffering bladder infections, bullying or suicide. Again,
it’s very interesting to compare these claims with Muollo-Gray’s petition
statement:
That aside what I want to get across is how blatantly
transphobic the school has been against me and how upsetting this whole
situation has been. There is no need to worry about other students safety in
this situation. It is me who has been forced to stop using certain bathrooms;
interrupting my learning and my school day. This whole situation has ended in
me being told I can use the gender neutral bathrooms that are available, and that
the school is looking to add more. But right now there are only four, and these
are at the outskirts of the school. As a girl I want to and should be able to
use the girls bathrooms. Why spend money on making bathrooms for me to be
segregated and out of sight of others when I can just go in the girls’ bathroom
free of charge? In the end it will be taxpayers forking out for this schools
transphobia.
The sentence which refers to ‘segregation’ is quite
misleading, according to this
article several of the previously female only facilities had been
converted into unisex facilities. Yet Muollo-Gray’s explanation is still far
more honest and grounded in reality than either of the hysterical Spinoff accounts.
What is at stake here is hurt feelings, the inconvenience of having to walk a
bit further than other students to access the toilet and the horrendous
possibility that the taxpayer would have to fork out precious funds to make
more unisex toilets. The most central reason is very clearly Muollo-Gray’s
presumed right to feel ‘validated and authentic’. Being excluded from female
only spaces is threatening to his psychological sense of ‘gender identity’.
The second
Spinoff article is titled ‘Teaching love: How to support your children
through questions about gender identity’. Full of love for the gender
non-confriming and gender diverse children of Aoteroa, Barbour Evans’ love does
not extend to embrace those unhappy with gender identity ideology:
We’ve seen “Laura” prodded into complaining by her (IMHO)
overbearing, bullying mother who raised a child to believe that transgender
people are subhuman in some way. We haven’t heard anything from the student
herself – a teenage girl with feelings and rights who does not deserve this
bullying from her peers."
I don’t know Laura or her mother, but from watching the ‘Ask
Me First’ video, it certainly is not clear that either of them view transgender
people as being ‘subhuman’. Laura’s mother refers to the ‘vulnerability’ of
teenage girls, and insists that males and females are ‘built differently’ and
therefore need private spaces. Laura talks about the ‘stressful and
embarassing’ time girls go through during puberty, and their increased need for
privacy. She says that younger girls with a history of abuse or trauma would be
particularly sensitive and ‘triggered’ by the presence of a male inside toilet
facilities. Both Laura and her mother also express concern for the precedent
set by this example, as it opens up the possibility of males using ‘gender
identity’ access to female spaces for exploitative or abusive purposes.
None of these concerns require adherence to religious
beliefs. It may be that some fundamentalist Christian people share these concerns,
but that fact in itself does not invalidate them. Transactivists such as Barbour
Evans and Matheson will invariably focus upon the supposed prejudice involved
with the concern about potential abuse, and will insist that there is no
evidence of any trans person ever harming anyone at any time. Unfortunately
they are wrong
about this, and there is considerable evidence that transgender males
commit violence
against women at about the same frequency as the male population as a
whole. Making this observation, and raising the issue of male violence and the
need for female only spaces is not ‘transphobic’ any more than it is ‘man
hating’.
Perhaps the most strikingly false statement is the second
part of Barbour Evans quote above, the suggestion that Muollo-Gray’s voice has
been completely absent from this affair. Teenage students as a rule have very
little say over how their schools are run. There are token gestures such as
student representatives on Boards of Trustees, but the reality for most teenage
kids is that of more or less complete powerlessness. They are compelled to wear
uniforms, attend classes, meet various behaviour requirements and so on.
Muollo-Gray’s influence over decisions made by the Marlborough school has been
massive. The petition, the media exposure and the trans lobby combined to
effectively make him more powerful than the school principal.
Psychological distress is an elusive thing to measure, but
in this case the apparent harms suffered by Muollo-Gray’s gender identity were counted as being far more weighty and significant by the school than any of the discomforts or fears held by
students such as Laura. Questioning the liberal orthodoxies of liberal Spinoff-doctors is an unpopular activity, but there is a compelling feminist case for doing so.
[For another left/feminist take on the Ask Me First story, check out Renee Gerlich's piece]
Thursday, 26 January 2017
The Intersex Continuum
I’m currently reading Alice
Dreger’s book ‘Hermaphrodites and the Medical Invention of Sex’ and trying to
clarify for myself a series of questions about sexual dimorphism and social
construction claims about biological sex. The book itself is excellent and
highly readable, and surely a valuable resource for anybody who is interested
in the history of how intersex people have been treated by society (and
specifically the medical establishment) over the course of the past two
centuries. Dreger is an advocate for intersex rights, and supports the rights
and humanity of intersex people. For these reasons I would recommend the book unhesitatingly
to anyone interested in this subject. My take on it here will be quite narrow
and critical however, because I don’t agree with the strong version of the ‘sex
as a social construction’ thesis which frames the historical narrative.
Dreger is an historian who does not
question the Michel Foucault / Judith Butler inspired poststructuralist model
of inquiry, and describes the history of medical definitions of sex through the
nineteenth and twentieth century without any reference to a universal, history
and culture independent account of ‘true’ sex. In a characteristic passage she
states:
So, if we want to sort, what should we employ as the necessary
and/or sufficient traits of malehood and femalehood? What makes a person male
or a female or a hermaphrodite? This is the problem. Today my own students,
college students in history classes, sometimes in exasperation ask these
questions of me at the end of a discussion of the history of sex, as if I am
holding the ‘real’ answer from them. ‘What really is the key to being male,
female, or other?’ But, as I tell them, … the answer necessarily changes with
time, with place, with technology, and with the many serious implications –
theoretical and practical, scientific and political – of any given answer. The
answer is, in a critical sense, historical – specific to time and place. There
is no ‘back of the book’ final answer to what must count for humans as ‘truly’
male, female, or hermaphroditic, even though the decisions we make about such
boundaries have important implications. Certainly we can observe some basic and
important patterns in the bodies we call ‘male’ and the bodies we call
‘female’. And the patterns we notice depend in part on the cognitive and
material tools available at a given moment. But the development of new tools
doesn’t get us closer and closer to some final, definite answer of what it is
to be ‘truly’ male, female or hermaphroditic. Instead it only alters the parameters
of possible answers. A hundred years ago we could not point to ‘genes’ in the
way we can today, but being able to point to genes doesn’t mean that we have
found the ultimate, necessary, for-all-time answer to what it means to be of a
certain sex[i].
The theoretical model is that of a continuum or spectrum, with
more male traits on one side and female traits on the other. In the middle is a
blurry bit which gets labelled ‘intersex’ or ‘hermaphroditic’ (I’ll use the 20th
century term ‘intersex’). Because the points which define boundaries between
male, intersex and female change over time according to changing medical
definitions and theories, ‘sex’ is a socially constructed form of categorisation.
To put things very crudely, the wider and more fluctuating the blurry middle
part is, the more arbitrary and less ‘real’ sex classes such as ‘male’ and
‘female’ are. There are at least three distinct claims which typically employ the
sex as continuum model as a fundamental premise:
1. Biological sex is socially
constructed
2. Biological sex is not real
3. Biological sex is mutable
and changeable
I'll come back to claim (2) at the end of this post, but for now I will restrict my focus to the question of the nature of the continuum.
Specifically, if we accept that sex can be thought of as a continuum, how big
and how ‘blurry’ is the intersex part in the middle?
The Frequency of
Intersex Conditions
Alice Dreger’s discussion of the
complexities and pitfalls of arriving at a firm and precise percentage are
worth recounting and careful consideration. Before she gives any statistical
estimate, Dreger lists a number of reasons why ‘it is almost impossible to
provide with any confidence an overall statistic for the frequency of sexually
ambiguous births[ii]’.
Specialist medical texts offer different frequency estimates, so we don’t know
which sources to trust. The samples upon which they are based might not be
representative of the entire human population. Sometimes very rare intersex
conditions cluster in particular geographic regions, so it is hard to work
these local variations into a global statistic. Environmental factors such as
hormone treatments complicate the picture further.
More fundamental considerations
include the question of what exactly counts as an intersex condition. Some
types of intersex conditions result in very clear anatomical ambiguity, whereas
other types are less severe or less obvious. Particular conditions may or may
not manifest themselves as cases of sexual ambiguity. Should we count all of
the people with all of the various conditions, or only the cases in which sex
is difficult to determine? Dreger’s account is also centred around the idea
that the category of ‘intersex’ is culturally and historically relative:
… such a
statistic [of intersex frequency] is always necessarily culture specific. It
varies with gene pool isolation and environmental influences. It also varies
according to what, in a given culture, counts as acceptable variations of
malehood or femalehood as opposed to forms considered sexually ambiguous. And
it varies according to what opportunities there are in a given culture for
doubts to surface and be articulated on record. […] Frequency is specific to particular
cultural spaces[iii].
Nevertheless Dreger does eventually
offer us a statistical estimate:
When I am
pressed for a rough statistic, I suggest that today, in the United States,
probably about one to three in every two thousand people are born with an
anatomical conformation not common to the so called typical male or female such
that their unusual anatomies can result in confusion and disagreement about
whether they should be considered female or male or something else. Anne
Fausto-Sterling, through recent research, estimates the incidence of intersexed
births to be in the range of 1 percent, although Fausto-Sterling warns that the
figure ‘should be taken as an order of magnitude estimate rather than a precise
count.’ (In other words, the number might be closer to one in a thousand.)[iv]
Although I appreciated the reasons
for Dreger’s reluctance to state an exact figure, I found this statement to be
very odd. Was it one in a thousand or one in a hundred? It looks like Dreger
might be inclined to a more conservative figure than Fausto-Sterling, but she
does not explain why.
It turns out that Anne Fausto-Sterling
is one of the authors of the only academic study which attempts to rigorously
answer this question:
We surveyed the medical literature from 1955 to the present for
studies of the frequency of deviation from the ideal male or female. We
conclude that this frequency may be as high as 2% of live births. The frequency
of individuals receiving corrective genital surgery, however, probably runs
between 1 and 2 per 1000 live births (0.1 – 0.2%)[v]
Again, there are two estimates: a
liberal figure of 2% and a conservative estimate which differs by an order of
magnitude – quite a big gap! In a paper written before this research was
carried out, Fausto-Sterling provides an even more ambitious frequency estimate,
together with an almost lyrical evocation of the ‘sex as a continuum’ thesis:
For some time medical investigators have recognized the concept of
the intersexual body. But the standard medical literature uses the term intersex as a catch-all for three major
subgroups with some mixture of male and female characteristics: the so-called
true hermaphrodites, whom I call herms, who possess one testis and one ovary
(the sperm- and egg-producing vessels, or gonads); the male
pseudohermaphrodites (the "merms"), who have testes and some aspects
of the female genitalia but no ovaries; and the female pseudohermaphrodites
(the "ferms"), who have ovaries and some aspects of the male
genitalia but lack testes. Each of those categories is in itself complex; the percentage
of male and female characteristics, for instance, can vary enormously among
members of the same subgroup. Moreover, the inner lives of the people in each
subgroup-- their special needs
and their problems, attractions and repulsions-- have gone unexplored by science. But
on the basis of what is known about them I
suggest that the three intersexes, herm, merm and ferm, deserve to be
considered additional sexes each in its own right. Indeed, I would argue
further that sex is a vast, infinitely malleable continuum that defies the
constraints of even five categories.
Not surprisingly, it is extremely difficult to estimate the
frequency of intersexuality, much less the frequency of each of the three
additional sexes: it is not the sort of information one volunteers on a job
application. The psychologist John Money
of Johns Hopkins University, a specialist in the study of congenital
sexual-organ defects, suggests intersexuals may constitute as many as 4 percent
of births[vi].
**
Although the four percent figure
has been shown to be unsupported by the available evidence, it is hard not to
conclude that Anne Fausto Sterling is quite keen on the idea that the
percentage of intersex people is a lot bigger than people would tend to expect.
Vast infinitely malleable continuums need room to blur boundaries and break
categories, hundredths are way better than thousandths for this purpose.
All of the intersex advocacy
organisations I have looked at use Fausto-Sterling’s figures, and the OII Australia site contains a detailed list of distinct conditions with respective percentages. The most up to date quoted figure seems to be 1.7%, taken from a book written by Fausto-Sterling in 2000, which bases its figures on exactly the
same academic source I quoted from above.
The OII Australia site also refers
to an academic paper critical of Fausto-Sterling’s frequency estimate by Dr. Leonard Sax. He argues that Fausto-Sterling’s definition of intersex as
including ‘anything that deviates from the Platonic ideal of male and female
bodies’ is far too broad. His definition of what counts as intersex leads to a
radically different frequency estimate:
‘The available data
support the conclusion that human sexuality is a dichotomy, not a continuum.
More than 99.98% of humans are either male or female. If the term intersex is
to retain any clinical meaning, the use of this term should be restricted to
those conditions in which chromosomal sex is inconsistent with phenotypic sex,
or in which the phenotype is not classifiable as either male or female. The
birth of an intersex child, far from being “a fairly common phenomenon,” is
actually a rare event, occurring in fewer than 2 out of every 10,000 births[vii].’
The OII Australia site argues
against Sax’s narrow conceptualisation, and favours a broad and inclusive
category which
“…encapsulates
a range of atypical physical or anatomical sex characteristics. These share in
common their non-conformance with medical and social sex and gender norms. This
non-conformance with stereotypical standards for male and female is why
intersex differences are medicalised in the first place and, while that remains
the case, it makes sense to us to include them in a definition of intersex.
The
difference between narrow and broad definitions in medicine is somewhat
ideological. The exclusion of some diagnoses that embody atypical sex
characteristics but not others seems, at least to us, to be irrational.
Intersex people do not share the same identities, but we share common ground in
the stigmatisation of our atypical sex characteristics.”
Clearly
there is a very important question here as to whether scientific distinctions
and definitions are purely ‘ideological’ or not. Also, the suggestion here that
stigmatisation itself might be a criteria for what counts as ‘intersex’ is
surely problematic: flat chested women and men with high pitched voices may
well face stigma, that doesn’t mean that they are ‘intersex’. Another
consideration is how ethical considerations intersect with scientific
questions. Intersex people face marginalisation and stigma both because they
have bodies which do not conform to biological norms and also because such
conditions are in fact unusual. If the level of ‘unusualness’ is reduced, this
would arguably lessen the sense of marginalisation and stigma. Should we base
our definition of ‘intersex’ on social justice considerations or scientific
theories?
Putting
these complex and contentious philosophical questions to one side, what types
of specific ‘moderate’ intersex conditions are we talking about here? Leonard
Sax rejects several of the various types of intersex condition identified by
Fausto-Sterling because they do not fit his scientific definition. By far the
biggest category he objects to is that of ‘Late Onset Congenital Adrenal Hyperplasia’ (LOCAH). This single
category accounts for a massive 1.5% of Fausto-Sterling’s 1.7% figure. What is
this condition and what are its symptoms?
The broad category of Congenital Adrenal
Hyperplasia (CAH) is described by a popular internet medical site as:
…an inherited (genetic) condition causing swelling of the
adrenal glands. The condition is associated with a decrease in the blood level
of a hormone called cortisol and an increase in the level of male sex hormones
(androgens) in both sexes. Some people get a mild condition that produces no
symptoms. Others (mainly baby boys) develop a severe form that can be
life-threatening. Medical treatment to correct hormone levels is available.
Surgery to improve the appearance of unusual genitalia (in girls) is sometimes
considered.
Leonard
Sax accepts that the severe (and very rare) form of CAH is a genuine intersex
condition, but he denies that the milder version of LOCAH is an intersex
condition. To sum up his analysis and put it bluntly: all men who have LOCAH
are unambiguously male. Sometimes they experience balding. Many women who have LOCAH have no symptoms. Of
those that do, symptoms include excessive body hair, infrequent periods and
acne. A small percentage of women with LOCAH have a larger than average
clitoris. If you want details, refer to his article through the link above
(it’s technical but not that hard to understand). I checked out a couple of the
studies Sax refers to. Dreger is correct when she warns about radically
different estimates from academic sources – the papers referred to by Sax quote
a frequency of around 1 or 2 in 1000 for LOCAH, very different from the 1.5%
figure. I’m not an expert in medical science, so it is hard for me to understand
this massive discrepancy. The best explanation appears to be that there is a
fairly wide spectrum of conditions which include higher than average levels of
male hormones in females (androgens), including rare conditions like LOCAH but
also including much more common conditions such as Polycystic Ovary Syndrome (PCOS).
The
conclusion to be drawn from these observations is that there appears to be a
contemporary trend towards a much broader and more liberal definition of
intersex conditions. This trend is in conflict with a more conservative
scientific definition of intersex. Radically different frequency estimates are
a consequence of this ideological conflict.
The
fact that this sort of conflict exists is consistent with Alice Dreger’s over-arching
postmodern narrative. She convincingly describes how doctors and medical
specialists strived throughout the late nineteenth and early twentieth century
for a very narrow definition of intersex. By defining males in terms of the
presence of testicular tissue, and females in terms of ovarian tissue, the
existence of ‘hermaphrodites’ was squeezed into an almost non-existent
category. People with ‘ovotestes’ are extremely rare (0.0012% according to
Fausto-Sterling), so by defining ‘hermaphroditism’ in this way, Victorian
sensibilities could be preserved. The desire to preserve a rigid sex binary was
linked to societal gender norms and fear of homosexuality. The existence of
intersex people was a threat to the social order which needed to be contained,
so narrow scientific definitions were sought after for reasons which were not
always purely scientific.
Searching
around the internet for alternative interpretations concerning intersex, I came
across this tumblr blog which includes the most broad and liberal conception of
‘intersex’ that I could find. The authors of the blog insist that medical
authorities should not have the sole right to determine who is and who is not
intersex, and that people with PCOS are definitely intersex if they want to
self define as intersex. Crucially, the question of whether someone is intersex
or not has more to do with identification than it does with any sort of medical
description. The ideological underpinning of this blog may well be indicative
of a new historical era. Dreger’s phrase for the Victorian approach towards
intersex people was ‘The Age of the Gonads’. This blog may well go down in
history as representative of ‘The Age of Trans’.
Is
sex really a ‘continuum’? Is sex ‘real’?
We
can think of sex as a continuum, with male traits at one extreme and female
traits at the other. All people will fall within the reach of two intersecting
normal curves, the left curve representing mostly males and the right curve representing
mostly females. The intersection in the middle is the group of intersex people.
The problem for this very abstract model is the fact that biological sex can be
conceptualised across a number of distinct axes. We could look at genetic factors
such as chromosones, gonadal tissue, secondary characteristics (such as body
hair), genital morphology, hormone levels or reproductive capacity. Every
factor would produce a different sort of graph. The huge complexity of intersex
conditions would defy any attempt to provide a realistic picture with such a simplistic
model.
Professor Daphna Joel refers to a ‘3 G’ model of sex which defines sex on the basis of
genetic, gonadal and genital factors. Using this model, 99% of all people fall
into one of two categories, male and female. Males have all of these physical
features: XY chromosones, testes, prostrate and seminal vesicles, penis and
scrotum. Females have all of these features: XX chromosones, ovaries, womb and
fallopian tubes, clitoris, vagina and labia. This model is described as ‘almost
perfect dimorphism’. Intersex conditions mean that we cannot say that sex is
absolutely dimorphic. Some conditions (such as those which involve ambiguous
genitalia) are cases of unusual intermediate phenomenon. Some conditions (such
as Complete Androgen Insensitivity) involve a set of mis-matching features (XY
chromosones and testes combined with female genitalia). Joel emphasises how
incredibly unusual this almost perfect dimorphism is: we can be 99% confident
for example that a baby born with a penis will have all the other features ‘matching’
(testes and XY chromosones). There are very few natural phenomenon with this
high degree of probabilistic uniformity.
I’m
going to conclude by quoting a passage from an academic paper by Caroline New,
who argues against the idea that intersex conditions support the notion that
sex is not ‘real’:
Postmodern
writers massively exaggerate intersexuality and misrepresent sexual attributes
as continuous rather than as distributed dimorphically, despite the variations
and overlaps on any one dimension.
Do these variations mean that sexual difference is not real? Once again
postmodern feminists have higher standards than anyone else for categorisation.
Hawkesworth maintains that females and males are not ‘natural kinds’ because
there is no set of properties possessed by every member of each of these groups
(1997). From a realist point of view,
‘natural kinds’ are so called because they tell us something about the causal
structures of the world. Causally important properties are contingently clustered,
but in such a way that the presence of some properties renders the presence of
others more likely – because there are common underlying properties that tend
to maintain the clusters of features (Keil, 1989:43). Biological kinds can
never meet the essentialist criteria postmodern thinkers implicitly require
(Boyd, 1992). Biology is messy and complex, and its regularities take the form
of tendencies rather than laws. In the case of sexual difference, these
tendencies are strong, ‘the genotypic and phenotypic division of bodies into
two sexes crosses species and millenia’ (Hull, forthcoming). Sexual difference,
then, is a ‘good’ abstraction. Pace deconstructionists, it brings together
characteristics that are internally connected, and the connections in question
are substantial, not merely formal (Danermark et al 2002).
[i]
Dreger, Alice D. ‘Hermaphrodites and the Medical Invention of Sex’. Harvard
University Press,1998.
[ii]
Ibid, p.40
[iii]
Ibid, p.42
[iv]
Ibid, p.42
[v] [Melanie Blackless, Anthony Charuvastra, Amanda Derryck, Anne
Fausto-Sterling, Karl Lauzanne, Ellen Lee, 2000, How sexually dimorphic are we? Review and synthesis , in American Journal of Human Biology 04/2000;
12(2):151-166.]
[vi] Anne
Fausto-Sterling, 1993, The
Five Sexes, in The Sciences 33: 20-25.
[vii] Leonard Sax, 2002, How
common is intersex? a response to Anne Fausto-Sterling, in
Journal of Sex Research, 2002 Aug;39(3):174-8.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)